Theories of Secularization: Rationalization and the Disenchantment of Society

what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

According to Weber, the rationalization of society led to the disenchantment of society and as a result religious motives for action were replaced by rational motives for action. This post considers arguments and evidence for and against this theory.

desacrilization religion.png

Max Weber argued that modern society was ‘characterized by rationalization and intellectualization, and, above all, ‘by the disenchantment of the world’ (1)

In traditional society, in which religious beliefs were strong, actions were primarily motivated by religious beliefs or superstitions. People were motivated to act out of a religiously motivated desire to go to heaven and avoid hell. (Or at least to avoid the social sanctions of those with religious power.)

However, with the Enlightenment and the Industrial revolution, the power of the of the church was increasingly questioned, and over a period of many years religious ways of thinking came to be replaced with more scientific or rational ways of thinking. Science and the scientific method became more central to social thought: knowledge was increasingly constructed through empirical, rational methods, rather than being dictated through religious channels.

From the Enlightenment onward, society went through a process of ‘disenchantment’ – the role of religion, magic, mystery, superstitions and faith became less prominent, and replaced by more rational motives for acting: rather than acting because faith leaders or religious tradition dictated that you should act in certain ways, without thinking about it, people were increasingly free to act for themselves. People en mass started to think more about how they should act, what they should do, and the best way to achieve their goals.

Four factors which encouraged rationalization and undermined religion

Wilson argued that the rational world view fundamentally undermined the religious worldview, because it was based on the principle of systematic procedures to assess ‘truth claims’, whereas religious knowledge could not be tested and verified.

Criticisms of the idea that rationalization undermines religion

(2) Wilson –  ‘Religion in a Secular Society’ (1966)

Share this:

Leave a reply cancel reply, discover more from revisesociology.

What Is Secularization?

  • Key Concepts
  • Major Sociologists
  • News & Issues
  • Research, Samples, and Statistics
  • Recommended Reading
  • Archaeology

Over the last few centuries, and especially in the last few decades, Western society has become increasingly secularized, meaning that religion plays a less prominent role. The shift represents a dramatic cultural change whose effects are still widely debated.

Secularization is a cultural transition in which religious values are gradually replaced with nonreligious values. In the process, religious figureheads such as church leaders lose their authority and influence over society.

In the field of sociology , the term is used to describe societies that have become or are becoming modernized —meaning that features of society such as the government, the economy, and schools are more distinct, or less influenced by religion.

Individuals within a society may still practice a religion, but it is on an individual basis. Decisions about spiritual matters are personal, family, or culturally based, but religion itself does not have a large impact on society as a whole.

In the Western World

Secularization in the United States is a hotly debated topic. America has been considered a Christian nation for a long time, with many Christian values guiding existing policies and laws. However, in the last few decades, with the growth of other religions as well as atheism, the nation has become more secularized.

In the United States, there have been movements to remove religion from government-funded daily life, such as school prayer and religious events in public schools. Further evidence of secularization can be seen in laws overturning prohibitions on same-sex marriage.

While the rest of Europe embraced secularization relatively early, Great Britain was one of the last to adapt. During the 1960s, Britain experienced a cultural revolution that reshaped people's views on women's issues, civil rights, and religion.

Over time, funding for religious activities and churches began to wane, reducing the impact of religion on daily life. As a result, the country became increasingly secularized.

Religious Contrast: Saudi Arabia

In contrast to the United States, Great Britain and most of Europe, Saudi Arabia is an example of a country that has not experienced secularization. Almost all Saudis identify as Muslims.

While there are some Christians, they are mainly foreigners, and they are not allowed to openly practice their faith. Atheism and agnosticism are forbidden, and such apostasy is punishable by death.

Because of strict attitudes toward religion, Saudi Arabia's laws, customs, and norms are closely tied to Islamic law and teachings. The country has religious police, known as Mutaween, who roam the streets enforcing religious laws regarding dress codes, prayer, and the separation of men and women.

Daily life in Saudi Arabia is structured around religious rituals. Businesses close several times a day for 30 minutes or more at a time to allow for prayer. In schools, approximately half of the school day is dedicated to teaching ​religious material. Almost all books published within the nation are religious books.

Future of Secularization

Secularization has become a growing topic as more countries modernize and shift away from religious values toward secular ones.

While many countries remain that are focused on religion and religious law, there is increasing pressure from around the globe, especially from the United States and its allies, for countries to secularize. Nevertheless, some regions have actually become more religious, including parts of Africa and Asia.

Some scholars argue that religious affiliation itself is not the best measure of secularization. They believe that a weakening of religious authority can occur in certain areas of life without a corresponding change in the religious identities of individuals.

  • How Our Aligning Behavior Shapes Everyday Life
  • Definition of Self-Fulfilling Prophecy in Sociology
  • Assessing a Situation, in Terms of Sociology
  • Collective Behavior
  • Matrifocality
  • Status Inconsistency
  • Social System
  • Overview of Sociobiology Theory
  • What Is a Cohort Effect? Definition and Examples
  • Definition of Typology in Sociology
  • What Is Groupthink? Definition and Examples
  • What It Means When a Variable Is Spurious
  • Definition of Cultural Relativism in Sociology
  • What Is a Microaggression? Everyday Insults With Harmful Effects
  • Understanding Resocialization in Sociology

Phil Zuckerman Ph.D.

What Is Secularism?

Although complex, it's pretty clear..

Posted August 28, 2018 | Reviewed by Devon Frye

Article 20 of Japan’s constitution, written in 1946, states the following:

“Freedom of religion is guaranteed to all. No religious organization shall receive any privileges from the State, nor exercise any political authority. No person shall be compelled to take part in any religious act, celebration, rite or practice. The State and its organs shall refrain from religious education or any other religious activity.”

In 2006, Richard Dawkins published The God Delusion, which has since sold approximately four million copies, and has been translated into numerous languages.

And just recently, a new survey found that 59 percent of people in Scotland are non-religious, with 37 percent being Christian and 4 percent being some other religion. Thus, for the first time in Scottish history, secular people well outnumber religious people.

Now, what do Japan’s constitution, Richard Dawkins’ international best-seller, and the high rate of irreligiosity in contemporary Scotland have do to with each other? Well, they all relate to secularism— a term that is growing in usage and becoming more and more relevant to the state of the world.

But what does secularism actually mean? What does it refer to?

Like any broad term meant to capture a phenomenon that is simultaneously social, cultural, historical, political, and philosophical, “secularism” is not one specific thing. Rather, secularism is constructed and employed by various people in diverse ways, connoting or signifying different ideas, processes, orientations, and occurrences. It’s usage and meanings are truly disparate, to be sure.

That said, we can delineate three main types or manifestations of secularism:

  • political secularism
  • philosophical secularism
  • socio-cultural secularism

All three overlap and are all related to one another, yet they definitely exhibit divergent traits and embody discrete meanings. It is thus best to think of these three forms of secularism metaphorically—like three branches stemming out from a common tree, united at root, and yet obviously distinct.

The first form of secularism is political secularism : ideologies and policies which seek to keep civic life free from religious domination or preference. That is, keeping government out of the business of religion and religion out of the business of government.

Such an end is articulated and achieved in various ways, some more successful than others—and some more repressively than others—to be sure. But what is important here is that this form of secularism is not necessarily synonymous with atheism or even anti-religion. Rather, it has to do with what place or status religion ought to have in government and civil society.

And from the letters of Thomas Jefferson to the First Amendment, and from France's ethos of laicité to the constitution of modern Japan, political secularism is championed by many religious and non-religious people as the best way to keep religion free and respected while simultaneously guaranteeing the equal rights of members of minority religions, or those with no religion at all.

Philosophical secularism is an umbrella term meant to capture that body of thought, writing, and activism which seeks to critique religion, debunk its claims, challenge its clerical authorities, and ultimately disabuse religious people of their religious faith and participation. From the ancient skepticism of Lucretius and Wang Chung to the best-selling books of the New Atheists, philosophical secularism entails the direct deconstruction of religious truth claims, criticisms of religious practices and leaders, and the promulgating of anti-theist polemics and anti-religious social protest.

Finally, socio-cultural secularism entails perhaps the most ubiquitous form or secularism: the weakening or diminishing of religion in society, in day-to-day life. Here, we’re talking about things like more stores being open on Sunday, people spending more time on the internet than studying the Bible, fewer people seeking to be priests or nuns, television shows or Broadway musicals making fun of religion with little backlash, and so on.

what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

At root, socio-cultural secularism is both a socio-historical and demographic phenomenon whereby more and more people are caring less and less about religion. It involves greater numbers of people in a given society living their lives in a decidedly secular manner, utterly oblivious or indifferent to supernatural things like God, sin, salvation, heaven, or hell; being distinctly disinterested in religious rituals and activities; and being less inclined to include or consider religion as a significant or even marginal component of their identity .

In short, political secularism is about the separation of Church and State, philosophical secularism is a school of thought that sees religion as a mistaken or malevolent phenomenon that ought to be debunked and discarded, and socio-cultural secularism refers to secularization: the weakening or loss of religiosity in day-to-day life over time.

For further reading, I’d recommend:

  • The Oxford Handbook of Secularism
  • How to be Secular
  • The Secular Outlook

Phil Zuckerman Ph.D.

Phil Zuckerman Ph.D., is a professor of sociology and secular studies at Pitzer College and the author of several books.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Psychiatrist
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find Online Therapy
  • International
  • New Zealand
  • South Africa
  • Switzerland
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Self Tests NEW
  • Therapy Center
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

September 2024 magazine cover

It’s increasingly common for someone to be diagnosed with a condition such as ADHD or autism as an adult. A diagnosis often brings relief, but it can also come with as many questions as answers.

  • Emotional Intelligence
  • Gaslighting
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience

Breadcrumbs Section. Click here to navigate to respective pages.

Secularism: The Basics

Secularism: The Basics

DOI link for Secularism: The Basics

Get Citation

Secularism: The Basics is a concise and engaging introduction to confusing and contradictory public discussions of secularism across the globe.

“Secularism” must be the most confused and convoluted term in the entire global political lexicon. From New York to Paris, to Istanbul, to Addis Ababa, to New Delhi, to Montevideo, there are countless examples of politicians, religious leaders and journalists, invoking the S-word in heated debates about public education, gender, sex, national symbols, and artistic freedom. In this lively and lucid book, Jacques Berlinerblau addresses why secularism is defined in so many ways and why it so ignites people’s passions. In so doing, he explores the following important questions: What does secularism mean? Why should we care about this idea? What are the different types of secularism and what are their histories? What are the basic principles of political secularisms? Why are secularism and Atheism often confused? What is the relationship between secularism and LGBTQ rights? What opposition are secularisms up against? What does the future hold for a concept millennia in the making, but only really operationalized in the twentieth century?

With a glossary of key terms, case studies, informative tables, and suggestions for further reading throughout, the book considers key philosophical, religious, anti-religious, post-modern and post-colonial arguments around secularism. This book is an ideal starting point for anyone seeking a readable introduction to the often-conflicting interpretations of one of our era’s most complex and controversial ideas.

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Chapter 1 | 12  pages, part i | 36  pages, the ten principles of political secularism, chapter 2 | 12  pages, who's on top, chapter 3 | 12  pages, “thought is free”, chapter 4 | 10  pages, “burning zeal”, part ii | 78  pages, frameworks of political secularism in global perspective, chapter 5 | 13  pages, american secularism, chapter 6 | 12  pages, french secularism, chapter 7 | 12  pages, indian secularism, chapter 8 | 11  pages, chapter 9 | 13  pages, atheist secularism, chapter 10 | 15  pages, embrace complexity, part iii | 62  pages, anti-secularism, lifestyle secularisms, and a case study, chapter 11 | 11  pages, anti-secularisms of the right, chapter 12 | 13  pages, anti-secularisms of the left, chapter 13 | 13  pages, lifestyle secularisms, chapter 14 | 12  pages, lgbtq rights in uruguay and secularstan, chapter 15 | 11  pages, love the referee.

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms & Conditions
  • Cookie Policy
  • Taylor & Francis Online
  • Taylor & Francis Group
  • Students/Researchers
  • Librarians/Institutions

Connect with us

Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067 5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG © 2024 Informa UK Limited

  • Tools and Resources
  • Customer Services
  • Contentious Politics and Political Violence
  • Governance/Political Change
  • Groups and Identities
  • History and Politics
  • International Political Economy
  • Policy, Administration, and Bureaucracy
  • Political Anthropology
  • Political Behavior
  • Political Communication
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Psychology
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Values, Beliefs, and Ideologies
  • Politics, Law, Judiciary
  • Post Modern/Critical Politics
  • Public Opinion
  • Qualitative Political Methodology
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • World Politics
  • Share This Facebook LinkedIn Twitter

Article contents

Secularism and religion.

  • Steven Kettell Steven Kettell Department of Politics and International Studies, University of Warwick
  • https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.898
  • Published online: 25 January 2019

The boundary between the religious and the secular spheres of life is contested in many parts of the world. From the latter decades of the 20th century, controversies over issues such as the legalization of same-sex marriage, assisted dying, and freedom of speech, as well as clashes around reproductive rights and equality issues, have all featured highly on national political agendas. Set against a backdrop of the “return of religion” to public life, these debates and tensions have given rise to the notion that secularism might be in a state of crisis or moving toward some form of post-secular condition. The term “secularism” is itself also contested. The precise nature of the “secular” and the “religious” spheres of life is subject to interpretation, and secularism in practice can be manifest in a number of ways. This ranges from exclusivist forms of secularism in countries such as the United States and France to inclusive secularism in the case of India. Supporters of a role for religion in public life maintain that religion provides a range of valuable public goods and gives individuals a sense of meaning and identity. Secularists, on the other hand, claim that the separation of church and state provides the best framework for upholding the rights and freedoms of all citizens regardless of their religion or belief.

  • return of religion
  • public sphere
  • politics and religion

Introduction

The boundary between the “religious” and the “secular” spheres of life is contested in many parts of the world. Controversies over issues such as the legalization of same-sex marriage, assisted dying, and freedom of expression, as well as clashes around reproductive rights and equality issues have all, from the latter years of the 20th century , featured highly on national political agendas. Supporters of a role for religion in public life maintain that religion provides a range of valuable public goods and gives individuals a sense of meaning and identity. As such, they argue that efforts to keep religion out of the public sphere are illiberal, intolerant, and undemocratic. Secularists, on the other hand, claim that the separation of church and state provides the best framework for upholding the rights and freedoms of all citizens regardless of their religion or belief.

This article explores the key themes and debates around the concept of secularism. It discusses the so-called return of religion to public life and the notion that these developments might constitute some kind of crisis of secularism or indicate a shift to a post-secular condition. It examines the core conceptual issues and problems in defining the term “secularism” itself. Some of the main arguments that are presented by supporters and critics of secularism in respect to the role that religion should have in the public sphere are explored. Claims that the West is now entering a “post-secular” phase are discussed.

The Return of Religion

The idea of secularization was one of the foundational assumptions of the social sciences. Many scholars believed that as the forces of modernity took hold, religious beliefs and practices would gradually lose social status, relevance, and hold on the lives of adherents. These forces included the rise of scientific rationalism, technological advancements, and the functional differentiation of the state, which, from the 19th century began to assume many of the social roles played by religion in areas such as health and education provision (Norris & Inglehart, 2004 ). For much of the 20th century these assumptions appeared to be validated. The postwar period was characterized by a progressive secularization of social and cultural life in most Western liberal democratic nations, with declines in all measures of religiosity (including attendance, membership, and beliefs) (Norris & Inglehart, 2004 ). However, by the turn of the new millennium scholars were becoming ever-more mindful of the fact that, far from disappearing, religious forces remained highly influential in political affairs. Events such as the 1979 Iranian Revolution, the emergence of the Christian Right in the United States, the collapse of state-led atheist regimes in the Soviet Union, and the rise of religious nationalism (as witnessed in countries such as Egypt, Turkey, India, and Pakistan) highlighted the multiplicity of ways in which religion and politics were intertwined. This “return of religion” to public life has raised questions about whether or not secularism is now in a state of crisis or perhaps moving into a “post-secular” phase (on these developments see Beckford, 2012 ; Casanova, 1994 ; Hjelm, 2015 ; Micklethwaite & Wooldridge, 2009 ).

The extent to which faith is involved in public life goes beyond high-profile political issues and debates (such as same-sex marriage or assisted dying) and can also be seen in the scale of legal regulations and processes concerning religion. A survey conducted by the Pew Research Center ( 2011 ), for example, found that 59 countries (30% of the world’s total) had specific laws or policies prohibiting blasphemy, apostasy, or defamation of religion, and that 44 of those countries enforced legal punishments for such behaviors that included fines, imprisonment, and even death. Further research by Pew ( 2015 ) has noted a considerable increase in government restrictions on religion, with 63% of the world’s population currently living in countries that are classified as having “high” or “very high” levels of restriction. Studies on the relationship between religion and the state have also highlighted a range of institutional and legal interconnections. According to research by Barro and McLeary ( 2003 ) 75 countries around the world had an official state religion at the turn of the millennium (40% of the world’s total), and many others had less formalized, but still influential, connections to religious organizations (Kettell, 2014 ). As Fox ( 2015 ) points out, no country in the world has a complete separation of church and state.

Conceptualizing Secularism

Debates around secularism are shaped by questions of conceptual definition. In one respect, the term “secularism” is a relatively easy and straightforward one to define. At its most basic level secularism simply entails a normative commitment to neutrality on the part of the state toward religious affairs, necessitating that the state should neither favor, disfavor, promote, nor discourage any particular religious (or nonreligious) belief and viewpoint over another. In institutional terms this is typically understood as meaning a commitment to upholding the separation of church and state.

Nevertheless, the simplicity of this notion belies more complex undercurrents. The idea of secularism as denoting a fixed, unchanging category of life predicated upon separate and clearly demarcated “secular” and “religious” spheres raises a number of issues. One of these is that the very concept of the “secular” is itself bound up with the binary opposite notion of the “religious.” Both terms emerged in western Europe during the Middle Ages: the term “religion” (deriving from the Latin “ religio ”) being initially used as a referent to the communal life of Christian monks, the term “secular” (from the Latin “ saeculum ”) referring to the world beyond these monastic communities. From the outset the two terms were constructed as opposites, with the “secular” being defined primarily in terms of what it was not —in this case: those things, places, and ideas that were distinct from the sphere of religious authority (e.g., see Taylor, 2007 ).

A related problem is that the concept of “religion” is itself ambiguous and contested. In many ways this too is linked to the historical and geographical context in which the term arose and developed, being used initially to describe a specifically western European form of Christianity. Alongside this, the sheer diversity of religious beliefs and behaviors makes it extremely difficult to produce a coherent and accepted definition of what “religion” actually is. Not all scholars are in agreement on whether religion involves particular types of beliefs, such as the existence of a god or gods (which many folk religions do not possess), certain types of practices, such as membership in a particular institution and attendance at a place of worship (which is far less relevant for religions such as Buddhism and Confucianism), or a commitment to follow a divinely inspired moral code (early hunter-gatherer societies, for example, had typically amoral forms of religion) (on these points see Boyer, 2004 ).

These conceptual issues have considerable implications. Some scholars have argued that the binary framework of distinct “secular” and “religious” spheres is so historically and culturally specific that the terms cease to have any real meaning outside of this particular, Western-centric context. Applying the terms to non-Western cultures and societies that fail to make such a clear-cut distinction (such as Islamic societies in which religion permeates all aspects of life) is sometimes said to be misleading and inappropriate. Some commentators, such as Timothy Fitzgerald ( 1987 ), have subsequently argued that the term “religion” is so problematic that it should be discarded altogether. Others have sought to highlight the ways in which the apparently separate categories of the “secular” and the “religious” are mutually constituted. As Talal Asad ( 2003 ) puts it, secularism constructs religion as its “other” in order to create its own sense of internal coherence. This involves imposing a fixed and unchanging concept of “religion” based on supernatural beliefs while presenting secularism as a rational category dealing with the natural world and the social order (on this point also see Mahmood, 2017 ). Other scholars, such as Charles Taylor ( 2007 ), have argued that secularism itself has theological origins and have pointed to the rise of monotheism—and especially the Protestant Reformation—as having paved the way for a progressive diminution in the role of the sacred and the notion of supernatural forces being present in everyday social and cultural life.

A further issue to be considered here is that there is no consensus as to what “secularism” actually means. The term was conceived by George Holyoake in the mid- 19th century as a way of denoting an ethical framework independent of religion while avoiding the negative connotations that were associated with the term “atheism,” which had long been considered to pose a threat to the social order. Thus, for Holyoake, secularism was defined as “the study of promoting human welfare by material means; measuring human welfare by the utilitarian rule, and making the service of others a duty of life . . . a series of principles intended for the guidance of those who find Theology indefinite, or inadequate, or deem it unreliable” (Holyoake, 1871 ). Other commentators, however, have described secularism in rather more negative terms. For some, such as Craig Calhoun ( 2011 ), secularism is seen as something akin to an ideology, a doctrine, or a political program, often with anti-religious connotations. According to Brett Scharffs ( 2011 ), secularism is little more than “a misguided, even dangerous, ideology that may degenerate into its own dystopian fundamentalism” (p. 109).

Varieties of Secularism

In terms of its practical and institutional arrangements, secularism can also be applied in a number of ways. Although the basic premise of secularism refers to the idea of state neutrality in respect to religious issues, the idea of “neutrality” remains open to interpretation. Thus, different forms of secularism can be said to exist along a continuum according to the extent to which the state maintains a distance from religion (a public sphere shorn of religious influence) or supports a position of equity toward religion (providing equal recognition and access for all religions in the public sphere). This distinction is sometimes described as one between “hard” and “soft” or “exclusivist” and “inclusivist” varieties of secularism (e.g., see Kettell, 2015 ; Kosmin & Keysar, 2009 ).

The precise form taken by secularism in any given context is shaped by a number of factors. These include a range of social, cultural, and political conditions (such as the composition, forms, and diversity of the religion or religions involved) as well as the specific features of the national and historical circumstances of the country in question. In western Europe the drive for the development of secularism was bound-up with a series of historical processes culminating in the creation of the territorially sovereign state, the rise of nationalism, and the growth of popular sovereignty. Central to much of this were the so-called religious wars from the 15th to the 17th centuries , one effect of which was to create a new set of ideas about the relationship between spiritual and temporal sources of authority (set out in the treaties of Westphalia in 1648 ) that prohibited rulers from intervening in the internal affairs of other states. Another critical effect was to create a particular view of religion as constituting a threat, or as a problem to be solved (see Taylor, 2007 ).

Nevertheless, there are significant regional variations. Most western European countries have tended to adopt an accommodating position, involving nuanced, pragmatic, and flexible relationships between the state and religion, and Christianity retains a privileged public role in a number of European states. A good example of this is the case of the United Kingdom. Although the United Kingdom is largely secular at the level of culture and society—the latest figures from British Social Attitudes ( 2017 ) have found that 52% of adults now describe themselves as being “non-religious”—it maintains close institutional links to Christianity through the formally established Church of England. The United Kingdom’s reigning monarch is simultaneously the head of the Church, and Anglican bishops continue to hold reserved seats in the upper chamber of the legislature (the House of Lords), a situation that is unique among advanced liberal democracies (Morris, 2009 ).

The U.K. context is in stark contrast to the situation in France. Here, a popular struggle against the power of an oppressive Catholic Church led (eventually, in the 1905 Law on the Separation of the Churches) to a model of secularism characterized by a public sphere free from any overt displays of religious expression and influence. In this form of secularism, known as laïcité , the French state keeps religion in a position of subordination, providing significant financial support for religious organizations (including the maintenance of churches and funds for religious schools) but reserving the right to intervene in religious affairs in order to uphold the broader values of the republic. In 2004 , for example, the French government imposed a ban on displays of religious symbols and items of clothing in public schools (following a high-profile case in which two Muslim schoolgirls were expelled for wearing the hijab) on the grounds that this was needed to ensure that all citizens obtained an equal education without external coercion. A full ban on wearing the Islamic veil (the niqab and the burqa) in public spaces was introduced in 2011 (on secularism in France, see Kuru, 2009 ).

A similar type of secularism to that practiced in France is also found in Turkey. Secularism here was introduced by the first president of the republic, the nationalist ruler Kemal Ataturk, who in 1923 established secularism as part of a project of modernization. The explicit aim in this context was to transform Turkey into a “Western style” state, and to create a public sphere that was free from religious influence. Set against the historical backdrop of the Ottoman Empire, in which religion had been a dominant social and political force, the Turkish secular arrangements included a variety of constitutionally enshrined controls and restrictions on religious practices, particularly involving the role of religion in the public arena (such as bans on displays of religious symbols and clothing in state buildings). Religious instruction and education in Turkey is also sanctioned by a state-controlled Directorate of Religious Affairs (Kuru, 2009 ).

Another form of hard, or exclusivist, secularism was developed in the United States. In contrast to French secularism (based on historic opposition to a powerful church), and Turkish secularism (used as a symbol of modernity), secularism in the United States was driven by high levels of religious pluralism and diversity. For many settlers fleeing religious conflict and persecution in western Europe, the American colonies were considered an attractive destination precisely because they would provide a greater degree of religious freedom. Yet in a significant number of cases, high levels of religious zeal in settler communities led to new forms of persecution, restrictions on religious liberty, and growing tensions between competing religious groups. One of the clearest illustrations of this is the case of the Massachusetts Bay Colony, in which citizens not conforming to the religious edicts of the dominant Puritan sect were persecuted, imprisoned, and in some cases even killed. Religious tests and qualifications for public office were also common and are still retained by a number of states today, despite being formally unconstitutional. Article 19 of the Constitution of the State of Arkansas, for instance, declares that: “No person who denies the being of a God shall hold any office in the civil departments of this State, nor be competent to testify as a witness in any Court.” Article 14 of the Constitution of the State of Mississippi holds that: “No person who denies the existence of a Supreme Being shall hold any office in this state” (on these points see Jacoby, 2004 ).

Faced with a growing need to secure peaceful coexistence between competing religious groups, the newly independent American states enshrined constitutional provisions for maintaining an exclusivist secular system. A key step in this direction was section 16 of the 1776 Virginia Declaration of Rights, overseen by Thomas Jefferson, which stated that “all men are equally entitled to the free exercise of religion, according to the dictates of conscience.” Following this, the First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution (ratified in 1791 ) provided the keystone for the new secular arrangements, declaring that: “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof.” This amendment prohibited the federal government from privileging any particular religion and supported the strict legal separation of church and state throughout the land. Although individual citizens remain free to express themselves and to use religion language and arguments in the public sphere, the United States (unlike France and Turkey) is constitutionally prohibited from intervening in religious affairs, and is thus unable to lend its support, or declare its opposition, to any particular religious (or nonreligious) worldview.

This constitutional separation of church and state in the United States has set the framework for a series of legal battles over the role of religion in the public sphere, leading to a number of high-profile court cases around the use of religious symbols and ceremonies in state buildings, land, and offices. Key examples here include cases brought by secularist campaign groups opposed to the displaying of a cross-shaped section of steel found in the wreckage of the World Trade Center in the partially state-funded National September 11 Memorial and Museum (a case that was eventually lost in 2013 ), opposition to the displaying of Christian nativity scenes in public parks, opposition to the exhibition and distribution of religious material in public schools (a case in 2012 saw a teenage atheist, Jessica Ahlquist, successfully file a lawsuit for the removal of a religious prayer banner), and opposition to displays of the Ten Commandments around courthouses (in 2011 an Ohio appeals court ordered Judge James DeWeese to remove a poster of the Ten Commandments from his courtroom, following a similar case involving the same judge in 2000 ). Long-standing (and as-yet unsuccessful) campaigns for removing the phrase “Under God” from the pledge of allegiance and “In God We Trust” from the U.S. currency (both formally introduced during the 1950s at the height of the Cold War against communism) are good illustrations of these campaign measures as well.

The kind of exclusivist secularism found in France, Turkey, and the United States can also assume more authoritarian and illiberal forms. The rise of communism during the 20th century saw states such as the Soviet Union and China enforce official scientific materialist doctrines for the state-led promotion of atheism and pursue an overtly anti-religious agenda, leading to significant restrictions on religious freedom. The rise of authoritarian forms of secularism was further shaped by the experiences of imperialism and decolonization. In countries such as Iraq, Egypt, Tunisia, and prerevolutionary Iran, for example, postcolonial nationalist regimes established authoritarian state structures that were often hostile to religious groups, viewing them as potential competitors for political power. In some cases, such as that of the Muslim Brotherhood (which was founded in Egypt in 1928 ), religious movements critical of the ruling regimes were banned and driven underground. While many secularists reject the idea that such political regimes warrant the label “secular,” because they fail to adhere to the principle of neutrality in religious affairs, critics of secularism often view the authoritarian turn as being implicit in the very notion of exclusivist secularism (on these themes, see Beattie, 2008 ; Mahmood, 2016 ; Woodhead, 2013 ).

On the opposite side of the spectrum is the inclusivist model of secularism found in India. In a similar fashion to the development of secularism in the United States, secularism in India was adopted as a means of dealing with the social dilemmas linked to high levels of religious pluralism and diversity. That said, in contrast to the U.S. model, which requires the state to maintain a clear legal distance from religion, the chief characteristic of the Indian version of secularism is that it upholds a notion of neutrality in which all religions are permitted equal access to, and a role in, the public sphere. In this context the state maintains a position of “principled distance,” intervening only to ensure that the overall balance of social values is maintained (see Bhargava, 2006 , 2010 ). At the same time, however, secularism in India also remains a contested issue, and since the rise to power of the Hindu nationalist Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP) in 2014 , growing concerns have been voiced about the role played by religion in India’s public life.

Supporters and Critics

Debates around the merits or otherwise of a role for religion in the public sphere tend to be polarized between supporters of a secular (usually exclusivist) state, who favor a public sphere free from religious influence, and those who argue that religion should play an active role in public life. Although there are varied arguments on both sides of this debate, the key claims tend to focus on a number of core themes. Arguments in favor of secularism center on claims that a secular state offers the best mechanism for guaranteeing the rights and freedoms of all citizens irrespective of their religion or belief. In contrast, arguments in favor of a role for religion in the public sphere are typically based upon the claim that religion provides a public good, and that denying religion a role in the public square is illiberal, undemocratic, and an infringement on religious freedoms.

The Case for Secularism

At its most elementary level, secularism is nothing more than the separation of church and state. This entails a commitment to a principle of neutrality by the state toward matters involving religion in public life. Thus, the state cannot favor or disfavor any particular religion or belief over another. But the principle of neutrality and the scope of the public sphere can be understood in very different ways. Many secularists understand the separation of church and state to mean that religion should exist on the same plane as all other political actors—that it should not be permitted a privileged role in public life but should otherwise be a free and equal participant in political debates. Others, however, take a more restrictive approach. Many supporters of exclusivist secularism frequently contend that, in diverse and pluralistic societies where citizens hold a variety of competing and sometimes incompatible worldviews—or what John Rawls ( 1971 ) termed “irreconcilable comprehensive doctrines”—actors making arguments in the public sphere should adopt a secular form of language and reasoning—a framework commonly described as “public reason.” From this perspective, arguments deployed by proponents of comprehensive doctrines (such as religious beliefs and worldviews) are said to be truly intelligible only to members of the particular group or community involved and will not therefore be universally accessible to all citizens. In contrast, the use of public reason—a set of criteria for concepts and language that the vast majority of reasonable citizens can understand and agree on—is said to be necessary for facilitating the kind of deliberative engagement and free exchange of ideas that a democratic society needs in order to function effectively. As such, secularists often maintain that religious (i.e., theologically based) forms of reasoning should be considered illegitimate for use in the public sphere or should be permissible only to the extent that secular (public reason) arguments are later forthcoming. Debates about the scope of the public sphere criteria, however, remain ongoing. Some secularists argue that public reason should be applied only to legislative and constitutional issues, but others maintain that the principle should be extended to embrace a conception of the public sphere that includes all matters of public discourse and political decision-making between citizens (on these issues see, e.g., Habermas, 2006 ; Quong, 2004 ; Rawls, 1997 ; Sajo, 2009 ).

A related argument that is often made in support of exclusivist secularism is that a secular state is a necessary condition for ensuring human rights and freedoms, including the freedom of religion. The central claim here is that secularism has a double-sided quality: simultaneously protecting the state from religion but also protecting religion from the state. So, citizens cannot be subjected to, or forced to abide by, religious imperatives, dictates, or laws. And by the same token, religious citizens themselves (at least in the private sphere) are free from interference from state officials, and thus have the freedom to worship and practice religion freely.

At the same time, secularists claim that religious organizations enjoy certain privileges that are often unfair and unjustified because they are not open and freely available to all citizens regardless of their beliefs. Thus, even in largely secularized societies, such as the United Kingdom, religious organizations are granted benefits that are not available to other social groups, such as trade unions or nonreligious charities, giving them a position in public life that can even, in some instances, influence public policy decisions. Such privileges in the case of the United Kingdom include the involvement of religious authorities in the upper legislature (allowing them to vote on policy decisions, such as the legalization of same-sex marriage), a prominent role the education system (allowing them to discriminate against children on the basis of their ascribed religion in the case of faith schools), and a variety of exemptions for religious groups on issues relating to tax and legal regulations (such as employment law and the provision of public services). One contentious issue for secular campaigners in the United States is the fact that many religious organizations are able to register as charities, allowing them to claim billions of dollars of public subsidy (Cragun, Yeager, & Vega, 2012 ). In Germany, the state automatically deducts a “church tax” from registered members of many religious denominations as part of its public subsidies for religion unless members expressly opt out (and in so doing risk losing access to religious services). Similar taxes are in place in several other European countries, including Austria, Italy, and Finland. In short, the overall argument from secularist campaigners is that religious views and organizations have enjoyed an excessively privileged and protected status for too long, and that they are no more deserving of special treatment than any other sectional interest group.

Evidence exists to support the view that secularism offers a way of increasing human rights and freedoms. For instance, research conducted by Kettell ( 2014 ) has found that countries with a state religion possess substantially lower levels of political rights and civil liberties than countries that do not possess a state religion. Political rights (such as free and fair elections, nondiscriminatory voter registration, and transparency of vote counting) were 27% worse in countries with a state religion, and civil liberties (including freedom of expression, belief, and association) were 37% lower. At the same time, countries with a state religion were found to have far higher (146%) levels of government regulation of religion (which is perhaps unsurprising, given that regulating religion is one of the reasons for having a state religion in the first instance), but also to have much higher (41%) levels of social regulation of religion (defined as the extent to which society itself seeks to impose restrictions or conformity of religious beliefs and practices), and 68% higher levels of religious persecution than countries without a state religion.

For these reasons, secularism has a broad-based appeal to both religious and nonreligious citizens alike. Indeed, while secularism is often presented by its critics as being anti-religious, its application in highly religious societies, such as the United States and India, shows this not to be the case. That said, some secularists do highlight the various ways in which religion can act as a negative social force. Key arguments here include the role of religion in cases of violence and conflict (including religiously inspired terrorism and intercommunal violence, but also cases of personal violence such as the parental withholding of medical treatment for children on religious grounds); instances of discrimination on issues of gender, sexual orientation, and reproductive rights (such as access to contraceptive healthcare and abortion); the role of religion in education systems (for instance, seeking to ban or distort discussion of scientific topics in the classroom, such as evolution), and high-profile cases of the abuse of religious power (such as the child abuse scandal in the Catholic Church).

Secularists who take this position often maintain that religious beliefs are especially pernicious in this respect, precisely because they are grounded in grand cosmic claims about the nature of reality, the afterlife, and moral endeavor. This, it is argued, creates a prime source of social “othering,” generating strong in- and out-group dynamics and mentalities that can lead to prejudice, intolerance, distrust, and violence. On this basis, it is argued that giving religion a role in public life opens the way to all manner of unwelcome sectarian and social divisions. In addition to these points, advocates of secularism sometimes also maintain that religion is not required for moral or ethical behavior, and that secular groups and societies can be just as effective (if not, in some cases, more so) at engendering trust and social cohesion as religious communities. Research by Zuckerman ( 2008 ), for instance, has found that secular societies tend to score better on a range of social indicators, such as levels of social inequality, family breakdown, violent crime, juvenile delinquency, drug abuse, and happiness, than religious societies.

The Case Against Secularism

Critics of exclusivist secularism commonly argue that the public reason criteria advocated by thinkers such as Rawls is unfairly restrictive, and that the public sphere should be open and accessible to religious views and arguments. One key claim here is that it is unreasonable (if not practically impossible) to expect citizens for whom religion forms an intrinsic part of their identity to exclude religious beliefs and motivations from political debates. According to its critics, this requirement violates the moral agency of religious citizens, forcing them to act in an inauthentic manner by requiring them to put their deeply held convictions and real motivations to one side and instead justify themselves in non-theological terms. As such, excluding religion from the public sphere is said to impose an unreasonable burden on citizens with religious beliefs because the need to translate arguments into public reason is distributed unequally, falling as it does on religious but not nonreligious citizens. Accordingly, some, such as the German social theorist Jurgen Habermas, have called for a broader “multi-dimensional concept of reason” and maintain that nonreligious citizens need to be more open and respectful of religious claims and ideas so that citizens can work together to find ways of reaching a “rationally motivated agreement” (Habermas, 2006 ; also see Asad, 2003 ; Wolterstorff, 2010 ).

In a similar fashion, critics of exclusivist secularism also argue that religious discourses or worldviews are no different from (and are therefore just as valid as) political worldviews or ideological perspectives such as “liberalism,” “socialism,” and “conservatism.” As such, prohibiting the use of religious arguments in the public domain is said to be profoundly illiberal and undemocratic, raising a barrier to the free flow of ideas within society. An exclusivist form of secularism is also said to contain intrinsic dangers, because suppressing people’s identities in such a fashion risks creating pressures that might lead to growing resentment, potentially driving otherwise-moderate people of faith into more extremist positions (see Stepan, 2000 ; Wolterstorff, 2010 ).

A related claim here is that religious views warrant a space in the public sphere because they are able to make a valuable contribution in terms of promoting positive social values. At the core of this argument is the notion that religion contains a moral dimension with the potential to benefit public discourse, such as highlighting issues of injustice, poverty, social inequality, and exclusion. Religion, in this sense, is considered to be a substantial public good, a repository of values and morality that can be drawn on for the benefit of all citizens. Commonly cited historical examples of this include the role of religious organizations in opposing slavery; their role in developing the civil rights movement in the United States; and the role of the Catholic church in opposing, and ultimately helping to bring down, the communist regimes of the Soviet bloc. Aligned with this is the popular assertion that religion offers a unique and beneficial source of social capital, helping to produce the “social glue” of public trust, cooperation, and cohesion that a democratic society needs in order to function effectively. A key argument in this regard is that religious citizens are more likely to become engaged in charitable activities, such as volunteering and making donations to good causes, than nonreligious citizens. This assumption has underpinned a range of public policy measures, including the promotion of faith-based initiatives in the United States and the attempt to foster a “Big Society” agenda in the United Kingdom based on allowing religious groups to assume a greater role in the delivery of welfare and public services (on these issues, see Smidt, 2003 ).

Another common argument put forward by critics of secularism is the claim that the idea of “neutrality” on which secular states are based is a myth. Instead, critics maintain that the relationship between religion and the public sphere will always reflect underlying power relations within a society, promoting and upholding certain values and interests rather than others. From this perspective, the idea of the supposedly neutral secular state is said to reflect a historically specific, Western bias that is rooted in certain ideas about the nature of politics and particular assumptions about the (privatized) character of religion. This, according to Modood ( 2010 ), views religion as a source of conflict and social tensions and is hostile to non-Christian forms of religion (typically Islam) that are unable or unwilling to confine themselves to the private sphere.

Related to this argument is the view that the concept of “reason” that has dominated secular Western thought since the time of the Enlightenment is itself problematic. A central point here is that, like the concept of “religion” itself, the claims of secular reason—such as the view that human beings have certain inalienable rights (for example, the right to life, liberty, property, and suchlike)—are also founded on unprovable, nonverifiable assumptions. Moreover, the idea of reason (and secularism itself) is said to suffer from the problem of “incompleteness,” being unable in and of itself to provide a basis for deriving a moral framework for human life and society. Without religion as an objective moral anchor, reason, it is said, will descend into a crass individualism, moral relativism, and an impoverished public discourse (on this see Kettell, 2009 ).

In recent years, many critics have complained about what they see as a militant, radical, intolerant, and illiberal form of secularism that is determined to marginalize religion and force it out of public life. Some of the most high-profile assertions here have come from the Roman Catholic Church. Pope Benedict XVI, for example, warned on several occasions that a radical and aggressive secularism was gaining ground in the United States and Europe, and that this development posed a grave threat to freedom of expression as well as traditional social values. In the United Kingdom the claim that religion is being driven out of public life has led to a number of high-profile court cases. In 2012 , four such cases involving alleged discrimination on religious grounds were taken to the European Court of Human Rights. Three of the cases were rejected, while the fourth (involving the case of an airline employee who wanted to wear a cross at work) was upheld, requiring that the uniform of the airline be amended to allow for reasonable accommodation (a change that the airline had already undertaken) (on the idea of “militant secularism” see Kettell, 2015 ).

The Future of Secularism

While these arguments about the merits or otherwise of secularism are well rehearsed, a relatively new feature of the debate is the view that Western democratic societies are now becoming increasingly “post-secular.” The “return of religion,” the endurance of religious communities, and the growth of religious influence in public life are said to have challenged the underlying assumptions on which secularism is based. As Habermas ( 2008 ) puts it: “Today, public consciousness in Europe can be described in terms of a ‘post-secular society’ to the extent that at present it still has to adjust itself to the continued existence of religious communities in an increasingly secularised environment” (p. 19). According to some scholars, these pressures are an indication that secularism itself is under strain or even experiencing some form of crisis. As Saba Mahmood ( 2009 ) writes: “What was once a latent schism between religious and secular worldviews has now become an incommensurable divide” (p. 836).

Although the exact contours and features of this new global landscape remain to be seen, a central claim is that the public reassertion of religion poses a significant problem for exclusivist models of secularism. One of the main dilemmas that now confronts secular Western societies is how to balance a commitment to neutrality in respect to religion with growing levels of religious pluralism, diversity, and assertiveness that are being driven by the increasingly interconnected and globalized nature of the modern world. The challenges posed to secular societies are becoming manifest in a number of ways. In the United States, the Christian Right, in close alliance with President Donald Trump, are actively pursuing an agenda of trying to undermine LGBT rights, restrict women’s access to reproductive healthcare, and push for greater religious influence in social and political life; in Turkey, secularism faces an attack by the governing regime of the Justice and Development Party (AKP), which has been seen by many commentators as pursuing an Islamist agenda (including the promotion of creationism in schools) that has gradually eroded the principle of state neutrality (e.g., see Kaya, 2015 ); and in India, the rise of Hindu nationalism fostered by the rule of the BJP has led to growing incidents of religiously fueled violence against members of minority faiths.

Debates around “post-secularism,” however, are also problematic. There is, as yet, no consensus among scholars as to what the concept itself actually means: whether it indicates some kind of reversion to traditional forms of religion, some kind of new coexistence between religious and secular worldviews, or a change in the form of religion itself as well as its relationship to the public sphere. Moreover, not all commentators are convinced that the idea of the “post-secular” is a useful or meaningful reflection of contemporary developments (see Beckford, 2012 ). Indeed, for some, claims about a return of religion are themselves called into question. Scholars such as Norris and Inglehart ( 2004 ) maintain that processes of secularization are continuing to unfold and that religion is continuing to decline in places where the forces of modernity hold sway. A key development in the United States, often held up as an example of the way in which religion can thrive in a technologically advanced society, has been a significant growth in the religiously unaffiliated (the so-called nones) since the late 20th century (Voas & Chaves, 2016 ). From this perspective, the notion of a “return of religion” and the growing assertiveness of religion in public life is seen as something of a rear-guard action by religious groups feeling the pressure of sustained decline and is not therefore interpreted as a sign that the institutional architecture of secularism is destined to come crashing down anytime soon.

  • Asad, T. (2003). Formations of the secular: Christianity, Islam, modernity . Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
  • Barro, R. J. , & McCleary, R. (2003). Religion and economic growth across countries. American Sociological Review , 68 , 760–781.
  • Beattie, T. (2008). The new atheists: The twilight of reason and the war on religion . New York, NY: Orbis.
  • Beckford, J. (2012). Public religions and the postsecular: Critical reflections. SSSR Presidential Address. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion , 51 (1), 1–19.
  • Bhargava, R. (2006). The distinctiveness of Indian secularism. In T. N. Srinivasan (Ed.), The future of secularism (pp. 20–53). New Delhi, India: Oxford University Press.
  • Bhargava, R. (2010). States, religious diversity and the crisis of secularism. Hedgehog Review , 12 (3).
  • Boyer, P. (2004). Religion explained: The evolutionary origins of religious thought . New York, NY: Basic Books.
  • British Social Attitudes . (2017). British social attitudes (34th report). NatCen Social Research .
  • Calhoun, C. (2011). Secularism, citizenship and the public sphere. In C. Calhoun , M. Juergensmeyer , & J. VanAntwerpen (Eds.), Rethinking secularism . Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
  • Casanova, J. (1994). Public religions in the modern world . Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
  • Cragun, R. , Yeager, S. , & Vega, D. (2012). Research report: How secular humanists (and everyone else) subsidize religion in the United States. Free Inquiry , 32 (4), 39–46.
  • Fitzgerald, T. (1987). A critique of “religion” as a cross-cultural category. Method and Theory in the Study of Religion , 9 (2), 91–100.
  • Fox. J. (2015). Political secularism, religion and the state: A time series analysis of worldwide data . New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
  • Habermas, J. (2006). Religion in the public sphere. European Journal of Philosophy , 14 (1), 1–25.
  • Habermas, J. (2008). Notes on post-secular society. New Perspectives Quarterly , 25 (4), 17–29.
  • Hjelm, T. (Ed.). (2015). God is back . London, UK: Bloomsbury.
  • Holyoake, G. J. (1871). The principles of secularism . London, UK: Book Store.
  • Jacoby, S. (2004). Freethinkers: A history of American secularism . New York, NY: Metropolitan Books.
  • Kaya, A. (2015). Islamisation of Turkey under the AKP rule: Empowering family, faith and charity. South European Society and Politics , 20 (1), 47–79.
  • Kettell, S. (2009). On the public discourse of religion: An analysis of Christianity in the UK. Politics and Religion , 2 (3), 420–433.
  • Kettell, S. (2014). State religion and freedom: A comparative analysis. Politics and Religion , 6 (3), 538–569.
  • Kettell, S. (2015). The militant strain: An analysis of anti-secular discourse in Britain. Political Studies , 63 (3), 512–528.
  • Kosmin, B. , & Keysar, A. (Eds.). (2009). Secularism and secularity: Contemporary international perspectives . Hartford, CT: Institute for the Study of Secularism in Society and Culture.
  • Kuru, A. (2009). Secularism and state policies toward religion: The United States, France, and Turkey . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mahmood, S. (2009). Religious reason and secular affect: An incommensurable divide? Critical Inquiry , 35 (4), 836–862.
  • Mahmood, S. (2016). Religious difference in a secular age: A minority report . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Mahmood, S. (2017). Secularism, sovereignty, and religious difference: A global geneology? Society and Space , 35 (2), 197–209.
  • Micklethwait, J. , & Wooldridge, A. (2009). God is back . London, UK: Penguin.
  • Modood, T. (2010). Moderate secularism, religion as identity and respect for religion. Political Quarterly , 81 (1), 4–14.
  • Morris, R. M. (Ed.). (2009). Church and state in 21st century Britain: The future of church establishment . London, UK: Palgrave.
  • Norris, P. , & Inglehart, R. (2004). Sacred and secular . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Pew Research Center . (2011). Rising restrictions on religion .
  • Pew Research Center . (2015). Latest trends in religious restrictions and hostilities .
  • Quong, J. (2004). The scope of public reason. Political Studies , 52 , 233–250.
  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Rawls, J. (1997). The idea of public reason revisited. University of Chicago Law Review , 64 (3), 765–807.
  • Sajo, A. (2009). Constitutionalism and secularism: The need for public reason. Cardozo Law Review , 240 , 2401–2429.
  • Scharffs, B. G. (2011). Four views of the citadel: The consequential distinction between secularity and secularism. Religion and Human Rights , 6 , 109–126.
  • Smidt, C. E. (2003). Religion as social capital: Producing the common good . Waco, TX: Baylor University Press.
  • Stepan, A. (2000). Religion, democracy, and the “twin tolerations.” Journal of Democracy , 11 (4), 37–57.
  • Taylor, C. (2007). A secular age . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Voas, D. , & Chaves, M. (2016). Is the United States a counterexample to the Secularizatiot Thesis? American Journal of Sociology , 121 (5), 1517–1556.
  • Wolterstorff, N. (2010). Justice: Rights and wrongs . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Woodhead, L. (2013). Liberal religion and illiberal secularism. In G. D’Costa , M. Evans , T. Modood , & J. Rivers (Eds.), Religion in a liberal state . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Zuckerman, P. (2008). Society without God: What the least religious nations can tell us about contentment . New York: New York University Press.

Related Articles

  • Liberalism and Religion

Printed from Oxford Research Encyclopedias, Politics. Under the terms of the licence agreement, an individual user may print out a single article for personal use (for details see Privacy Policy and Legal Notice).

date: 12 September 2024

  • Cookie Policy
  • Privacy Policy
  • Legal Notice
  • Accessibility
  • [195.158.225.230]
  • 195.158.225.230

Character limit 500 /500

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction
  • The revolution of modernity
  • The West and the world
  • The dual revolution
  • General features
  • Economic change
  • Population change
  • Urbanism as a way of life
  • Work and the family
  • Social structure

Secularization and rationalization

Social problems.

  • Western and non-Western routes to modernity
  • One world or many
  • Developments in economic and social structure
  • New patterns of urban life

Max Weber

  • What was Haile Selassie I known for?
  • How did Haile Selassie I die?

Encyclopaedia Britannica First Edition: Volume 1, Plate XLIII, Figure 1, Astronomy, Solar System, Equation of Time, Precession of Equinoxes, Earth, orbit, ecliptic, apogee, perigee, line of apsides, mean anomaly, tropical year, Sydereal, Julian

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • Brooklyn College - Modernization Theory and the Comparative Study of Societies: A Critical Perspective
  • The Ohio State University Pressbooks - Keys to Understanding the Middle East - Modernization Versus Westernization
  • National Center for Biotechnology Information - PubMed Central - The impact of globalization and modernization of laws and theories on the modernization of philosophy in Vietnam: mediating role of modern societies
  • Social Science LibreTexts - Modernization
  • Pressbooks Create - Modernization Theory
  • Simply Sociology - Modernization Theory: Definition and Examples
  • Table Of Contents

At the most abstract level of analysis, modernization leads to what Max Weber called “the disenchantment of the world.” It calls into question all the superhuman and supernatural forces, the gods and spirits, with which nonindustrial cultures populate the universe and to which they attribute responsibility for the phenomena of the natural and social worlds. In their place it introduces as a competing cosmology the modern scientific interpretation of nature by which only the laws and regularities discovered by the scientific method are admitted as valid explanations of phenomena. If it rains, or does not rain, it is not because the gods are angry but because of atmospheric conditions, as measured by the barometer and photographed by satellites.

In short, modernization involves a process of secularization ; that is, it systematically challenges religious institutions, beliefs, and practices, substituting for them those of reason and science. This process was first observable in Christian Europe toward the end of the 17th century. (It is possible that there is something inherently secularizing about Christianity, for no other religion seems to give rise spontaneously to secular beliefs.) At any rate, once invented in Europe, especially Protestant Europe, secularization was carried as part of the “package” of industrialism that was exported to the non-European world. Wherever modern European cultures have impinged, they have diffused secularizing currents into traditional religions and nonrational ideologies .

Although secularization is a general tendency or principle of development in modern societies, this does not imply that religion is driven out altogether from society. In fact, as one of the most modernized countries in the world, the United States is also among the world’s most religious. Against a deep background of tradition, modernization inevitably leaves many religious practices in place and may even stimulate new ones. Religious rituals, such as Christian baptism and church weddings, persist in all industrial societies; the church may, as in England and Italy , continue to play an important moral and social role. The majority of the population may hold traditional religious beliefs alongside more scientific ones. There may even be, as in the United States and in industrializing societies such as India , waves of religious revivalism that involve large sections of the population.

It is nonetheless true that all such religious phenomena, real as they may be in the lives of believers, lose their centrality as an organizing principle for the society as a whole. As compared with their place in traditional society, religious practices increasingly take on the character of individualized activities. They no longer embody that crucial legitimating power that religious activities have in all nonindustrial societies. To many, baptisms, church weddings, and other rituals persist as much for social reasons as from belief in their religious significance.

Secularization is but one manifestation of a larger cultural process that affects all modern societies: the process of rationalization . While this process is epitomized by the rise of the scientific worldview, it encompasses many more areas than are usually associated with science. It applies, for instance, to the capitalist economy, with its rational organization of labour and its rational calculation of profit and loss. It applies also to artistic developments, such as the rational application of the geometry of perspective in painting and the development of a rational system of notation and rational harmonic principles in music. For Max Weber, the most careful student of the process, it referred above all to the establishment of a rational system of laws and administration in modern society. It was in the system of bureaucracy , seen as the impersonal and impartial rule of rationally constituted laws and formal procedures, that Weber saw the highest development of the rational principle. Bureaucracy meant a principled hostility to all traditional and “irrational” considerations of person or place, kinship or culture . It expressed the triumph of the scientific method and scientific expertise in social life. The trained official, said Weber, is “the pillar both of the modern state and of the economic life of the West.”

Weber was aware that bureaucracy has two faces. It can also be despotic and irrational in actual operation. The triumph of the principle does not guarantee its strict performance in practice. Rationalization is a process that operates at the highest, most general level of social development . It would be surprising if its effects were to be found in every nook and cranny of modern society. Everywhere one should expect to find the persistence of nonrational and even antirational attitudes and behaviour. Superstition is one example; the occasional rise of personal, charismatic leadership breaking through the rationalized routines of bureaucracy is another. These should not be thought of simply as vestiges of traditional society. They are also the expressions of essential needs, emotional and cultural, that are in danger of being stifled in a scientific and unillusioned environment .

Weber stressed another significant point. Rationalization does not connote that the populations of modern societies are, as individuals, any more reasonable or knowledgeable than those of nonindustrial societies. What it means is that there is, in principle, scientifically validated knowledge available to modern populations, by which they may, if they choose, enlighten themselves about their world and govern their behaviour. In practice, as Weber knew, such knowledge tends to be restricted to scientifically trained elites. The mass of the population of a modern society might in their daily lives be relatively more ignorant than the most uneducated peasants, for peasants usually have a comprehensive and working knowledge of the tools they use and the food they consume, whereas modern people may well use an elevator without the slightest idea of its working principle or eat food manufactured in ways and with materials of which they are totally unaware.

As with bureaucracy, so with most other features: they show the two faces of modernity . One is dynamic , forward-looking, progressive, promising unprecedented abundance, freedom, and fulfillment. The other shows the dark side of modernity, the new problems that modernity brings in its wake by virtue of the very scale and novelty of its achievements. Social progress is matched by social pathology.

Thus, the historic achievement of becoming able to feed a large population brings with it crowding, pollution, and environmental destruction. Quiet, privacy, and space become scarce and increasingly treasured commodities. Massed together in cities, seeking rest and recreation , the populations of industrial societies force open the whole world to tourism. Soon every rural haven, every sunswept coast, is turned into an administered holiday camp, each a uniform replica of the rest. The industrial principle of mass production and distribution can readily be turned from the production of goods to that of services, including those of leisure and entertainment.

Urban-industrial life offers unprecedented opportunities for individual mobility and personal freedom. It also promises the attainment of dazzling prizes, in wealth and honours, for those with the enterprise and talent to reach for them. The other side of the coin is the loneliness of the city dweller and the desolation of failure for those many who cannot win any of the prizes. As Durkheim analyzed it, the individual is placed in the pathological condition of anomie . He experiences “the malady of infinite aspirations.” The decline of religion and community removes the traditional restraints on appetite, allowing it to grow morbidly and without limit. At the same time the competitive modern order that stimulates these unreal expectations provides insufficient and unequal means for their realization. The result is an increase in suicide, crime , and mental disorder .

Industrial work , too, exacts a high price for the enormous increase in productivity brought about by the intensified division of labour . Karl Marx offered the most systematic analysis of this price under the heading of “ alienation .” Industrial workers feel estranged from the activity of work because their tasks are so fragmented, undemanding, and meaningless. They do not realize themselves, their human potential, in their work. Unlike traditional craft work, for instance, it does not call on their constructive and creative faculties. Industrial workers also feel alienated from the product of their work, for they have no control over its manufacture nor over the terms and conditions of its disposal. As the dynamic sum of its parts, the industrial system of production is phenomenally powerful, but this power is achieved at the cost of reducing one class of those parts, the human workers, to mere “hands,” mere semblances of humanity. Eventually, Marx hoped, the surplus wealth produced by the industrial system would free workers altogether from the necessity of work, but until that time the degraded condition of workers would be the most eloquent testimony to the dehumanization wrought by the system.

Marx’s optimism about the future was perhaps as excessive as his pessimism about his present. But he was by no means the only one who felt that industrial society demanded too high a price of many of its members. Repeatedly, industrialism was found to have created new and apparently ineradicable pockets of poverty. Despite steady economic growth , it was the persistent finding throughout the industrial world that between 15 and 20 percent of the population remained permanently below officially defined levels of poverty . It appeared that industrialism by its very mechanism of growth created a “new poor,” who for whatever reason—deprived backgrounds, low enterprise, low intelligence—were unable to compete according to the rules of the industrial order. The communal and kinship supports of the past having withered away, there was no alternative for the failed and the rejected but to become claimants and pensioners of the state.

There were other victims, too. The small nuclear family offered, to a greater extent than ever before, the opportunity for intense privacy and emotional fulfillment. But the very intensity of these relationships seemed to put an intolerable burden on it. Added to that, the family survived as the only remaining primary group in society, the only social unit where relationships remained primarily personal and face-to-face. Elsewhere bureaucratic or commercial relationships prevailed. The nuclear family was called upon to do all the work of restoration and repair of its members on their return from the impersonal, large-scale, bureaucratic world of work and, increasingly, play. Under this unprecedented pressure it began to show all the classic symptoms of distress. Adolescent alienation and teenage rebellion became accepted features of modern family life. Divorce rates soared; and when people sought to remarry—“the triumph of hope over experience”—their second marriages proved even less stable than their first. There was a steady increase in the incidence of one-parent families, usually headed by a woman.

Modernization, finally, put a number of new political and cultural problems on the agenda. The plethora of choices about how to spend leisure time and the urbanization of life gave rise to so-called postmaterialist values in advanced industrial societies, reflecting the greater importance attached to quality-of-life issues such as entertainment, self-improvement, and the environment. The decline of local communities , the great growth in the scale of all social institutions, and the acceleration of political centralization put a strain on civic loyalties and the willingness of people to participate in political life . As mass political parties came to monopolize civic life, individual citizens retreated increasingly into private life. Political apathy and low turnouts at elections became matters of serious concern, calling into question the democratic claims of modern liberal societies. A similar concern centred on the spread of mass communications , which dominated the cultural life of modern societies in the early and mid-20th century. The uniformity and conformity bred by the press, radio, and television threatened—albeit passively rather than directly—the pluralism and diversity on which liberal society prided itself and which it regarded as its chief security against totalitarian challenge.

Together, political and cultural centralization and uniformity were interpreted as evidence of the creation of a “ mass society .” Tocqueville had warned that individuals lacking strong intermediate institutions with which to identify would become atomized and in their anonymity and powerlessness might look to the protection of strong leaders and strong governments. Once more, this outcome had to be seen as a possibility, not an inevitability. Pluralism also remained strong in many societies. But the rise and success of totalitarian movements in some industrial societies showed that the tendencies were real and suggested that they were present in some degree in all modern societies.

Secularism Vs Secularization: What's the Difference?

Robert Harding Picture Libr. Ltd/Creative RF / Getty Images

  • Belief Systems
  • Key Figures in Atheism
  • M.A., Princeton University
  • B.A., University of Pennsylvania

Although secularism and secularization are closely related, there are real differences because they do not necessarily offer the same answer to the question of the role of religion in society. Secularism is a system or ideology based on the principle that there should be a sphere of knowledge, values, and action that is independent of religious authority, but it does not necessarily exclude religion from having any role in political and social affairs. Secularization, however, is a process which does lead to exclusion.

Process of Secularization

During the process of secularization, institutions throughout society - economic, political, and social - are removed from the control of religion . At times in the past, this control exercised by religion might have been direct, with ecclesiastical authorities also having authority over the operation of these institutions - for example, when priests are in charge of the nation's only school system. Other times, the control might have been indirect, with religious principles constituting the basis for how things are run, such as when religion is used to define citizenship.

Whatever the case may be, either those institutions are simply taken away from religious authorities and handed over to political leaders, or competing alternatives are created alongside the religious institutions. The independence of these institutions, in turn, allow individuals themselves to be more independent of ecclesiastical authorities - no longer are they required to submit to religious leaders outside of the confines of a church or temple.

Secularization & Church / State Separation

A practical consequence of secularization is the separation of church and state - in fact, the two are so closely associated that they are almost interchangeable in practice, with people often using the phrase "separation of church and state" rather when they mean secularization. There is a difference between the two, though, because secularization is a process that occurs across all society, whereas the separation of church and state is simply a description of what occurs in the political sphere.

What the separation of church and state means in the process of secularization is that specifically political institutions - those associated with varying levels of public government and administration - are removed from both direct and indirect religious control. It does not mean religious organizations cannot have anything to say about public and political issues, but it does mean that those views cannot be imposed upon the public, nor can they be used as the sole basis for public policy. The government must, in effect, be as neutral as possible with respect to divergent and incompatible religious beliefs, neither hindering nor advancing any of them.

Religious Objections to Secularization

Although it is possible for the process of secularization to proceed smoothly and peacefully, in reality, that has often not been the case. History has shown that ecclesiastical authorities who have wielded temporal power have not readily handed over that power to local governments, especially when those authorities have been closely associated with conservative political forces. As a consequence, secularization has often accompanied political revolutions. Church and state were separated in France after a violent revolution; in America, the separation proceeded more smoothly, but nevertheless only after a revolution and creation of a new government.

Of course, secularism has not always been so neutral in its intent. At no point is it necessarily anti-religious , but secularism does frequently promote and encourage the process of secularization itself. A person becomes a secularist at the very least because he believes in the need for a secular sphere alongside the religious sphere, but more likely than not he also believes in the superiority of the secular sphere, at least when it comes to certain social issues.

Thus, the difference between secularism and secularization is that secularism is more of a philosophical position about the way things should be, while secularization is the effort to implement that philosophy - even sometimes with force. Religious institutions may continue to voice opinions about public matters, but their actual authority and power are restricted entirely to the private domain: people who conform their behavior to the values of those religious institutions do so voluntarily, with neither encouragement nor discouragement emanating from the state.

  • What Is Secularism?
  • Definition: Religious Authority Vs. Secular Authority
  • Is Christmas a Religious or Secular Holiday?
  • Nonbeliever vs. Atheist
  • Background on the Investiture Conflict and Controversy
  • What is an Antipope?
  • What's the Difference Between Nontheism and Atheism?
  • What's the Difference Between Religion and Spirituality?
  • The Difference Between Atheists and Agnostics
  • Introduction to Theism and Atheism
  • Comparing the Ten Commandments
  • Thou Shalt Not Commit Adultery
  • Natural Theology vs. Theology of Nature
  • Religion vs. Religious
  • Defining the Characteristics of Religion
  • Religion vs. Superstition

IMAGES

  1. Understanding Secularism

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

  2. What is secularism, 1o points,

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

  3. Unit -3

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

  4. What is Secularism? 3 types of secularism: political, philosophical, socio-cultural

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

  5. PPT

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

  6. Secularism

    what is the basic thesis of secularism quizlet

VIDEO

  1. Class 11 Political Science Notes Chapter 8 Secularism

  2. What is Secularism?

  3. In defense of secularism 1/3

  4. Charlotte Ross

  5. In defense of secularism 2/3

  6. Expecting Questions|What Secularism is and is Not|Romila Thapar|Sem 1 BA BSC BCOM

COMMENTS

  1. Government/Economics

    Terms in this set (4) What is the basic thesis of secularism? That religion is a private matter that should stay out of public spaces. Why do many Christians view abortion as murder? Because they believe that every person from conception bears the image of God. Is secular the same as neutral?

  2. BJU American Government Chapter 3 Flashcards

    Study with Quizlet and memorize flashcards containing terms like John Locke, Natural Law, Establishment Clause and more. ... Secularism's basic thesis. Religion is a private matter that should not be discussed in public. Lay investiture controversy. When the superior would invest the churchman with political and spiritual responsibilities.

  3. Secularism Flashcards

    Study with Quizlet and memorize flashcards containing terms like What does a secularist belive., What is the basic description of secularism., The secular view of history holds that religion in general, and Christianity in particular, is responsible for what? and more.

  4. Theories of Secularization: Rationalization and the Disenchantment of

    According to Weber, the rationalization of society led to the disenchantment of society and as a result religious motives for action were replaced by rational motives for action. This post considers arguments and evidence for and against this theory. Max Weber argued that modern society was 'characterized by rationalization and intellectualization, and, above all, 'by

  5. PDF The three elements of the secularization thesis

    SECULAR (epistemic category) and SECULARISM (political doctrine) • The secular denotes a mode of knowing which is neutral with respect to religious commitments or "visions of the good" and thus open and common to all. • The state, emerging out of the conflict of religious wars, finds in the secular a kind of "lowest common

  6. Secularization: Definition and Examples

    Secularization is a cultural transition in which religious values are gradually replaced with nonreligious values. In the process, religious figureheads such as church leaders lose their authority and influence over society. In the field of sociology, the term is used to describe societies that have become or are becoming modernized —meaning ...

  7. What Is Secularism?

    article continues after advertisement. Philosophical secularism is an umbrella term meant to capture that body of thought, writing, and activism which seeks to critique religion, debunk its claims ...

  8. Secularism: The Basics

    Secularism: The Basics is a concise and engaging introduction to confusing and contradictory public discussions of secularism across the globe. "Secularism" must be the most confused and convoluted term in the entire global political lexicon. From New York to Paris, to Istanbul, to Addis Ababa, to New Delhi, to Montevideo, there are countless examples of politicians, religious leaders and ...

  9. What is secularism?

    Abstract. The British social reformer George Jacob Holyoake (1817-1906) coined the word 'secularism' to describe his this-worldly approach to personal morals, to philosophy, and to the of society and politics. A modern definition, provided by scholar Jean Baubérot, sees secularism made up of three parts: separation of religious ...

  10. Gov. Section answers Flashcards

    Study with Quizlet and memorize flashcards containing terms like What is the basic thesis of secularism?, Why do many Christians view abortion as murder?, Is secular the same as neutral? Why or why not? and more.

  11. Introduction: The Study of Secularism

    Worldliness, absence of religious principle or feeling. Secular or nonsacred character; absence of connection with religion. A secular person, social activity, or cultural institution is worldly, concerned for matters of daily life. To study the secular and secularity is to study the temporal and worldly.

  12. Chapter 3 THE SECULARIZATION THESIS AND THE SECULAR STATE ...

    secular paradigm altogether.3 Notions of the secular state, like the democratic state, should be clear enough to protect basic political goods yet open enough to allow the unique religious heritage and national character of each state and citizen to express itself in the public sphere. The Secularization Debate

  13. Secularism and Religion

    The idea of secularism as denoting a fixed, unchanging category of life predicated upon separate and clearly demarcated "secular" and "religious" spheres raises a number of issues. One of these is that the very concept of the "secular" is itself bound up with the binary opposite notion of the "religious.".

  14. Secularization and rationalization

    In such a way do the multinationals illustrate, even embody, the interdependence of core and periphery nations. Modernization - Secularization, Rationalization: At the most abstract level of analysis, modernization leads to what Max Weber called "the disenchantment of the world.". It calls into question all the superhuman and supernatural ...

  15. Secularization

    As phrased by José Casanova, this "core and the central thesis of the theory of secularization is the conceptualization of the process of societal modernization as a process of functional differentiation and emancipation of the secular spheres—primarily the state, the economy, and science—from the religious sphere and the concomitant ...

  16. CH 5: The Secularization Thesis and its Challenges

    CH 5: The Secularization Thesis and its Challenges. It is widely recognized now that the process of secularization encompasses three separate but related sets of social changes with regard to religion, and changes at one level may not be matched at the other. For example, while the influence of religious institutions in society may be lessening ...

  17. PDF Martin Luther on Secular Authority: The Powers of Princes versus the

    157 Martin Luther on Secular Authority: The Powers of Princes versus the Obligations of Subjects Nick Vaughn In 1523, Martin Luther drafted his treatise, Secular Authority: To What Extent Should It Be Obeyed, in which he presented what scholars have dubbed "The Two Kingdoms Doctrine" because of Luther's interpretation of how God rules over the world in two different ways.

  18. Secularism Vs Secularization: What's the Difference?

    Thus, the difference between secularism and secularization is that secularism is more of a philosophical position about the way things should be, while secularization is the effort to implement that philosophy - even sometimes with force. Religious institutions may continue to voice opinions about public matters, but their actual authority and ...

  19. Gov. SQ 40 Flashcards

    Study with Quizlet and memorize flashcards containing terms like Religion is a private matter that should stay out of public spaces, They believe every person, from conception, bears the image of God, No. ... What is the basic thesis of secularism? They believe every person, from conception, bears the image of God. Why do many Christians view ...

  20. Secularism Flashcards

    what is secularism ? Click the card to flip 👆. Secularism is the separation from religion and state. India is a secular country. Click the card to flip 👆. 1 / 6.

  21. Secularization, R.l.P.

    the secularization thesis, was entirely candid on this point. Having outlined the macro aspects of secularization, Berger (1967: 107-108) noted: Moreover, it is implied here that the process of secularization has a subjective side as well. As there is a secularization of society and culture, so there is a secularization of consciousness.